Heresy or Hermeneutics
the case of nasr hamid abu zayd
Charles Hirschkind
This paper
focuses on the debate that followed Cairo University's decision to refuse
tenure to a professor of Arabic Language and Literature, Nasr Hamid Abu Zayd,
in light of an unfavorable report by the tenure committee entrusted to review
his scholarly work. Supporters of Abu Zayd quickly brought the case to national
attention via the Egyptian press, thereby precipitating a storm of often shrill
writings from all sides of the political spectrum, in both journalistic and
academic media. Subsequently, as an Islamist lawyer tried to have Abu Zayd
forcibly divorced from his wife on the grounds that his writings revealed him
to be an apostate, the foreign media also picked up the story and transformed
the case into an international event. [1]
In what follows,
I will focus on one corner of this debate concerning contrastive notions of
reason and history, issues which, I wish to argue, are deeply implicated in the
forms of political contestation and mobilization occurring in Islamic countries
today. Such topics seldom appear in discussions that take Islamic movements, or
Islamic revival, as their object, an omission perhaps attributable to the
conceptual frames informing these discussions. The idea of a social movement
presupposes a self-constituting subject, independent from both state and
tradition; a unilinear progressive teleology; and a pragmatics of proximate
goals: namely, the spatiotemporal plane of universal Reason and progressive
History, territory of the modern man. Such an actor must fulfill the Kantian
demand that reason be exercised autonomously and embodied in the sovereign
subject. In such a framework, Islam never satisfies these modern demands and
thus must always remain somewhat outside the movement of history as a lesser
form of reasoning. In contrast, one may argue that the protagonist of a
tradition of inquiry founded on the divine text is necessarily a collective
subject, one who seeks to preserve and enhance his/her own exemplary past.
Indeed, the assumption of a fundamental opposition between reason and religion,
one central to the historical development of both of these modern concepts
during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, has entailed that
investigations into the rationalities of religious traditions have rarely been
viewed as essential to the description or explanation of those religions.[2]
Consequently, to pose a question in regard to Islam generally means that one
must either be asking about politics (the not- really-Islam of
"Islamism," or "political Islam") or about belief, symbols,
ritual, and so on, but not about styles of reasoning.
Within political
economy discussions of oppositional movements in the Middle East, for example,
Islam is generally viewed as little more than the culturally preferred idiom
through which opposition, be it class or otherwise, may be expressed.[3]
Unquestionably, the best of these studies have told us much about the kinds of
material conditions--the specific intersections of capital and power--that have
enabled or undermined arguments, movements, and forms of practice, including,
among others, Islamic ones.[4]
Founded upon the same set of Enlightenment assumptions mentioned above, these
writings have provided convincing accounts of the kinds of modern forces
transforming the contemporary political structures of the Middle East, but are
ill-equipped when it comes to analyzing those dimensions of social and
political life rooted in non-Western traditions.
One way to
approach this latter, as Asad has argued, is to understand Islam as a
discursive tradition: i.e., as an historically evolving set of discourses
embodied in the practices and institutions of Islamic societies and hence
deeply imbricated in the material life of those inhabiting them.[5]
Such a perspective requires that statements and/or arguments integral to the material organization of Islamic social forms, and grounded in slow-changing historical structures, be distinguished from those rhetorical performances which lack this longitudinal embeddedness.[6]
The approach being suggested here should by no means be confused with what is commonly referred to as a culturalist argument. Such arguments generally foreground the category of identity, stressing the authenticity of certain cultural practices and symbols for those subjected to the destructive and destabilizing forces of modernization. In contrast, to discuss a discursive tradition implies attention to specific articulations of material processes, structures, and practices, including practices of reasoning and speech, embedded in the society under study.
Such a perspective requires that statements and/or arguments integral to the material organization of Islamic social forms, and grounded in slow-changing historical structures, be distinguished from those rhetorical performances which lack this longitudinal embeddedness.[6]
The approach being suggested here should by no means be confused with what is commonly referred to as a culturalist argument. Such arguments generally foreground the category of identity, stressing the authenticity of certain cultural practices and symbols for those subjected to the destructive and destabilizing forces of modernization. In contrast, to discuss a discursive tradition implies attention to specific articulations of material processes, structures, and practices, including practices of reasoning and speech, embedded in the society under study.
The fact that
traditions of Islamic argumentation and reasoning stand in an oblique relation
to much of the current use of Islam by people seeking to legitimize their
activities or sell their products underscores the importance of making this
type of distinction.[7]
When a business enterprise calls itself Islamic, in what sense does it
intersect with the long-standing discourses of Islam? Admittedly, usages of
this type by banks, airlines, political candidates, or government ministries
may have a direct impact on current definitions and interpretations of Islamic
practice and, as such, might be of considerable interest to someone
investigating the role of Islamic rhetoric in Egyptian political and popular
culture. Study of a discursive tradition, however, directs our attention to the
coherence and continuity of a set of discourses, so as to map the
transformations which they undergo, including those brought about under the
pressure of more powerful traditions. Thus, the last few hundred years have
seen an ongoing attempt to adapt the conceptual resources of Islam in order to
accommodate, understand, and achieve practical mastery over a reality
increasingly organized by discourses whose historical locus and most formidable
bases of power lie in the West.
In short, the
type of movements appearing in Middle Eastern countries requires an analysis of
the contending traditions, both liberal and Islamic, which inform modes of
political thought and action in the area. Abu Zayd's work gains particular
value in this regard: as a modernist attempt to overcome the divisions
separating these traditions, his writings reveal some of the conceptual
problematics which such a project entails. In this respect, there are numerous
parallels between Abu Zayd and earlier reformers such as Qasim Amin or Taha
Hussayn, Muslim writers whose advocacy of Western social and political models
went beyond what many of their contemporaries considered acceptable and
reasonable within the Islamic framework. At the core of this project, as I
shall explore in this paper, lies an ongoing argument concerning the bases and
proper scope of reason on the one hand, and the historical status of divine
texts on the other.
modernizing islam
Abu Zayd's writings address a number of issues
central to Islamic thought, including methods of Quranic interpretation, the
authority of religious scholars, and the appropriate role of religion in
contemporary life. Given the recent turmoil, violence, and challenges to
political authority in Egypt, it is not surprising that once his work drew mass
media attention, it became a rallying point for a number of political currents.
Roughly speaking, liberal commentators tended to frame the issue as one of
"intellectual freedom": Abu Zayd, in their view, was being punished
for having subjected to critical scrutiny the sacred tenets of
institutionalized Islamic authority. Comparisons to Salman Rushdie were
frequently drawn, while those Cairo University professors who had opposed Abu
Zayd's tenure were repeatedly charged with "intellectual terrorism."
Moreover, Abu Zayd's assertion that differences between the Mubarak government
and the Islamic opposition were only of degree, and not of kind, inasmuch as
both were founded upon the same authoritarian, anti-humanist conceptual
foundations, drew considerable praise from many on the Egyptian left.
Uncomfortable in either government or Islamist camps, and with the grounds for
a politically viable Marxist critique long since eroded, many left-leaning
intellectuals were encouraged by this elaboration of a liberal alternative.
According to
Islamic writers, on the other hand, Cairo University had been correct in its
decision, as Abu Zayd's work was indeed an affront to a long tradition of
respected Islamic scholarship, as well as a grave injustice to its primary
text, the Quran. Many saw in Abu Zayd another example of a Marxist, secularist
campaign to expunge Islam from the universities, as well as from society in
general.
Much of the
calmer discussion focused on two intertwined arguments central to Abu Zayd's
work, one concerning the historical status of the Quran, and the other
addressing the relation of reason [`aql] to religion [din]. A
review of this discussion reveals some of the conceptual fault lines that cut
across Egyptian society and structure political praxis.
A key point of
departure for Abu Zayd's argument[8]
is the idea that, once the Quran was revealed to Muhammad, it entered history
and became subject to historical and sociological laws or regularities [qawanin].
Irreversibly rent from its divine origins, the text became humanized [muta'annas],
embodying the particular cultural, political, and ideological elements of
seventh-century Arabian society:
The
Quran--the pivotal point of our discussion so far--is a fixed religious text,
from the standpoint of the literal wording, but once it has been subjected to
human reason [al-`aql
al-insani] it becomes a "concept" [mafhum], which loses its
fixedness as it moves and its meanings proliferate....It is imperative here
that we affirm that the state of the original sacred text is a metaphysical one
about which we can know nothing except that which the text itself mentions and
which always comes to us via a historically changing humanity.[9]
From the moment
of its enunciation, the divine text was shaped, and continues to be reshaped,
through the operation of human reason, such that the distance now separating it
from the divine is so vast as to render the text all but human.[10]
In other words,
the abrupt break with the divine occurring at the moment of revelation results
in the total secularization of the text, which henceforth becomes a book like
any other: "Religious texts, in the final analysis, are nothing but
linguistic texts, belonging to a specific cultural structure and produced in
accord with the rules of that culture."[11]
The historical
reality of which the Quran partakes in Abu Zayd's narrative is that defined by
a realist sociology, a space of ideological contestation wherein autonomous
subjects of interest (individuals, groups, classes) compete with each other for
short-term political and economic goals. The logics of such a space imply, for
example, that a correct understanding of the Quran must begin by situating it
in the context of Qurayshi domination and hence as part of the
ideological apparatus undergirding that particular class of merchants; this
follows from the simple (if erroneous) observation that, "[the principle
of] divine sovereignty simply results in the sovereignty of religious men--in
the end, nothing but human beings with their own biases and ideological
inclinations."[12]
Indeed, throughout Abu Zayd's argument, the downgrading of truth claims to the
status of ideology, a function of culture and class interest, grounds a
reinterpretation of religion emphasizing hidden motives and personal ambitions.
Such a perspective requires us to conclude, for instance, that the claims to
correct, true knowledge made by religious specialists must in reality be a ruse
by which this group (and now the state interests which they serve) secures its
power and authority.[13]
Moreover, such an argument renders the idea of Islam as a coherent historical
object untenable by emphasizing the considerable variation in Islamic practices
and interpretations over time and geographical area. As Abu Zayd states, to
posit such unity is to "contradict the actual history of Islam, one which
has witnessed a plurality in trends, currents, and camps which emerged for
social, economic, and political reasons."[14]
The objects,
actors, forms of knowledge, and action which constitute history in this account
completely evacuate the divine from (humanly knowable) religion. Not
surprisingly, it is the liberal subject who largely fills the resultant void, a
substitution effected historically, from this perspective, by the process of
progressive enlightenment, the gradual journey from superstition and error to
progress, science, justice, and freedom; a movement which, moreover, humanizes
inasmuch as man abandons those traditions that made him subordinate to texts
and their interpreters and increasingly asserts himself as master of his own
destiny.[15]
Notably, for this modern promethean subject, it is literature, not revelation,
which opens out onto the unknown and transcendent. Consider, for example, the
following contrast drawn between literary and religious texts:
It is obvious
that religious texts don't pose the same problematic in regard to
"intention" as do literary texts; or rather, they pose it at a
different epistemological level, one constituted by the objective
condition--social, economic, and political--which circumscribed the production
of these texts and defined their field of application, and hence, their
original and fundamental signs and meanings.[16]
That is to say,
whereas a notion of the transcendent is no longer germane to the task of
explaining and understanding religious texts (which only require
socio-historical analysis), it finds continued application in that ineffable
inner world of individual writers and readers, an indeterminate space defined
by the modern idea of literary intention. Clearly, it is a short step from
these observations to the claim that "secularism [al- `almaniyya],
in its essence, is nothing but the true interpretation and scientific
understanding of religion."[17]
Indeed, once one has learned to differentiate the metaphysical text from the
real historical one, and exclude the former as a suitable object of knowledge,
the possibility is opened up to analyze the Quran as one would any other
"sign system," be it poetry, behavior patterns, or even "fashion
trends," as Abu Zayd provocatively suggests.[18]
Abu Zayd
identifies his own work as an attempt to establish an "objective" [maudu`i],
"scientific" [`ilmi] framework for the analysis and
interpretation [tafsir] of religious texts, a goal which evaded the
Islamic thinkers who preceded him, as they failed to address adequately the
historical dimension of their project. The hermeneutic approach he advocates
consists of two moments, each to be placed in dialectical relation to the
other.[19]
One entails the recovery of the original meaning [dallatuhu al-asaliyya]
of the text-cum-cultural-artifact, by placing it within the socio-historical
context of its appearance.[20]
The other aims to clarify the contemporary socio-cultural frames and practical
goals which motivate and guide interpretations, so that one may distinguish the
ideological content of those interpretations from the original historical
meaning. A "productive" reading results when these two steps are
placed in relation to each other in an ongoing dialectic, "a pendular
movement between the dimensions of Ôorigin' [asl] and Ôgoal' [ghaya],
or between Ôsign' [dallala] and Ôsignificance' [maghza]."[21]
Yet, despite the
supposedly dialectical structure of this interpretive method, we find that it
never really strays outside the horizon of modernity. For, as Abu Zayd asserts
in his introduction, "religion, when correctly understood, is that which
in accord with a scientific analysis and interpretation denies the false and mythical,
while preserving whatever promotes progress [taqaddum], justice [`adl],
and freedom [hurriyya]."[22]
Foregrounded throughout his work and central to the argument, these modernist
goals set the criteria for what is to be considered an acceptable
interpretation and in so doing close off all other historical horizons.
Furthermore, the idea of a hermeneutic open to meanings embedded in a distant
past makes little sense in light of Abu Zayd's negative judgment on the utility
of past history. He writes:
[the tendency
of religious discourse] to obliterate the historical dimension is obvious in
its assumption of a congruence between the problems of the present and those of
the past, and the application of past solutions to present conditions.
Moreover, recourse to the work of earlier scholars, and the attribution of a
sacred status to their texts, further effaces this historical aspect and leads
to the deepening of human alienation and the covering over of practical
problems rooted in reality.[23]
If, as Abu Zayd
suggests, the past is that which pulls people away from their real selves as
reason-guided individuals acting in a present of pragmatic, short-term goals,
then his call for Muslims to continue to interrogate the Quran may best be
understood as a tactical response to the social context of his writing, and
thus as accessorial to the argument itself
conceptual origins
The idea that past examples cannot guide us in
confronting our present problems emerged in Europe during the eighteenth
century and was made possible, in part, by a gradual shift in the concepts
organizing historical experience.[24]
While there is not space here to review the complex series of events involved
in this transformation, I shall mention a few key displacements that paved the
way for the modern concept of history. Prior to the eighteenth century, history
had referred to an account, an edifying example drawn from events that had
already taken place. Over the course of this century, the semantic field of the
term extended to include not only the idea of an account, but also that of the
event itself, the incident in its occurrence as opposed to any oral or written
rendition of it. This intertwining of representation with event meant that
accounts were now expected not simply to report of things past, but to capture
"history itself," as a coherent, all-embracing reality, a meaningful
whole. To do justice to this fuller reality, historians had to draw upon the
representational resources of other scholarly fields, such as poetics, ethics,
and rhetoric, as well as developing new rules of evidence and methods for
organizing historical data. As Kosselleck notes: "Without the ability to
read past events and texts at several levels, that is to separate them from
their original context and progressively reorder them, an advanced
interpretation of confusing historical reality would not have been
possible."[25]
Thus, theories, hypotheses, and interpretive frameworks--such as the economic
and the sociological, as we see in Abu Zayd's work-- became essential tools for
the historian's task, one which contrasted significantly with earlier forms of
historical representation that did not face the same demands for a fuller
meaning and coherence. As History began to eclipse God as the omnipotent force
in the universe, the older accounts became inadequate to represent the
intensified, and increasingly secularized, historical reality. Rather than the
divine text illuminating the vicissitudes of history, now history itself became
necessary to explain the text, which henceforth was increasingly subjected to
mundane criticism. Importantly, this new omnipotence and compulsion attributed
to history, as scholars of post-coloniality have emphasized, was not simply a
matter of semantics: the discourses of history became one of the key political
technologies of the nation-state and its various institutions (e.g.,
educational, juridical, administrative) and central to the construction of
those practices by which citizen-subjects came to recognize themselves and act
as such.[26]
Lastly, once the
philosophy of progress equipped history with a temporality not grounded in
natural cycles (such as the movement of planets or the life-spans of rulers),
it largely stripped past examples of their capacity to instruct. As the past
stopped shining a light onto an ever-accelerating future,[27]
reason alone remained adequate to the task of illuminating this latter. To meet
this challenge, however, reason had to be freed first from the shackles of
tradition and religion so as to acquire the sort of mobility or capacity for
improvisation adequate for organizing a future of probabilities, unforeseen
opportunities, and unpredictable outcomes.
In the opinion
of Abu Zayd, one he shares with many orientalist scholars, the
"backwardness" of Muslim societies owes precisely to a failure to
engage directly (i.e., without reliance on texts) with this mundane space of
pragmatic interventions, rational calculation, and short-term planning.[28]
Thus, he writes, "when social and political conflicts are transferred from
the field of reality to that of texts, human reason becomes subordinate to the
text";[29]
or similarly, "the principle of textual arbitration [tahkim] led to
the demise of independent reasoning, transforming it into an appendage of the
text itself."[30]
These judgments emerge directly from the logic of the precepts of the modern
idea of history, one conceding no space for the divine or for those practices
which presuppose its existence.
It is worthwhile
here to compare the positions taken by Abu Zayd and certain arguments on the
issue of toleration put forward by John Locke. Writing in the seventeenth
century, a period marked by the great sectarian conflicts, Locke was one of
those who articulated a theoretical perspective from which incommensurable
understandings of religious practice could be rendered neutral with regard to
politics.[31]
Adopting a quite literal understanding of the mind/body distinction, he argued
that inasmuch as divine worship was essentially a matter of the inner
disposition of the believer toward God and actions of the body were therefore
without consequence in regard to salvation, religious practices could be
ascribed the same legal status as all other social practices and thus be
legitimately regulated by civil authority. As McClure notes:
In the face
of conscientious considerations that order alternative religious practices
hierarchically, Locke's defense of toleration forwards a cognitive secular
ground for leveling such differences, specifically by deploying the categories
of empiricist epistemology as the source of a new distinctive "difference"
that privileges a factual civil discourse over its scripturally framed
theological other. To put the point another way, Locke's Letter advances a way of converting
sectarian "differences" in religious matters into
"diversity," by constituting a realm of civil facticity to dissolve
those hierarchical and intrinsically relational conscientious
"differences" of religious practice into equivalent and independent,
that is to say, separate, equal, and diverse, alternative religious
communities.[32]
McClure
insightfully observes Locke's ability to render religious claims mere
speculation and to privilege the domain of earthly "reality" about
which a true positive knowledge may be produced. This domain of specifiable
objects and social behaviors may then be regulated according to the idea of
social utility, that is, in keeping with the bourgeois subject's interests of
life, liberty, and property. Religion, in its material embodiment as a set of
practices and texts, loses all epistemological privilege, joining other mundane
objects subject to this regulation. Religion, once ascribed the status of a
"sign system" as in Abu Zayd's work, may then be taken up by the
historian as an entirely suitable object of historical analysis and
determination. As Chakrabarty has described, this construction of historical
objects requires that:
we be able to
deny them their contemporaniety by assigning them to a specified period in a
calendrical past, an act by which we split the present into the
"modern" and the "traditional" or the
"historical," and thereby declare ourselves to be modern....History
is therefore a practice of "monumentalising" objects--from documents
to sculptures--of simultaneously acknowledging and denying their existence in
our "own" time.[33]
To render the
Quran as "monument" means to redefine its relationship to the
present, to accord it new areas of relevance and irrelevance so as to
circumscribe the claims that may be made in its name to the private sphere of
individual conscience.
While Abu Zayd
is obviously writing upon the same empiricist conceptual terrain established by
Locke and his successors, certain differences stand out. Specifically, whereas
in Locke we find the believer's encounter with the divine restricted to the
"inner worship of the heart," in the case of Abu Zayd, the divine
never enters human experience at all. Unable to survive the passage into
socio-cultural embodiment, God remains outside knowledge,[34]
history, and the real. Religion, consequently, to the extent that it speculates
on the unknowable and remains moored to a tradition of such speculation, can
only distract us from the practical affairs which constitute reality, its
reason always remaining counter to the logics governing this domain.
My object in
this paper so far has been to demonstrate the degree to which the deployment of
certain sociological assumptions transforms and reconfigures the object
"religion," or "Islam," along specific lines. Studies of
such modernist reworkings of non- modern traditions have begun to shed an
important light upon one aspect of the process by which Western modernity has
transformed the world.[35]
I will now turn to some of the critical responses to Abu Zayd's work, published
during the height of the controversy, which may help elucidate a different
conception of history, the divine, and religious argument in contrast to the
one discussed so far.
some dissenting views
Abu Zayd's scholarly Writings were subject to a
wide variety of criticisms, including charges of gross historical error, of
being political manifestos rather than serious, scientific analyses, and of
addressing subjects outside the author's field of expertise. More relevant to
the present discussion, however, are those criticisms concerning the bases of
rational argument within the Islamic tradition, an issue foregrounded by many
authors, including `Abd al-Sabur Shahin, the Cairo University professor whose
report on Abu Zayd's work was the most influential. In his report, Shahin
accuses Abu Zayd not only of failing to understand certain principles of
Islamic theology but, more inexcusably, of rejecting them outright in a manner
incompatible with a commitment to Islam and, hence, unacceptable for a Muslim
scholar.[36]
The idea that a certain kind of critical inquiry depends upon one's commitment
to a religious community, as Shahin suggested in the report, stands in sharp
contrast to the emphasis on detachment and neutrality characteristic of the
tradition of empirical science. In the eyes of his liberal defenders, comments
that questioned Abu Zayd's moral commitment were entirely irrelevant to the
scholarly assessment of Abu Zayd's works and simply represented unscrupulous
attempts to discredit him personally. However, the attribution of unscholarly
intentions to Abu Zayd should not distract us from taking the argument itself
seriously: namely, that the practice of reason occurs within a social context
and, thus, presupposes and requires commitment to the principles which sustain
that context.[37]
As one writer responding to Abu Zayd argues,
for any
critical engagement [ijtihad]
with the religious texts to be acceptable and legitimate, it must begin with a
commitment to the text....Every critical activity which seeks to undermine and
destroy the shari`a texts, is not protected under the notion of
intellectual freedom, but rather falls within the range of that which society
must prohibit and prevent, especially where the constitution identifies Islam
as the religion of state and the shari`a as the primary source of law.[38]
For many
authors, Abu Zayd's denial of the divinity of the Quran constituted proof of
his lack of commitment to Islam. Faith in the sacred status of the Quran, they
argued, stands as the central and ineluctable tenet of Islam, the foundation
stone upon which Islamic society and civilization rest. Thus, while Abu Zayd's
suggestions concerning hermeneutic method, the importance of clarifying
historical contexts, or the need to weed out superstition and error were seen
by many to fall within the realm of reasonable argument, his rejection of the
Quran's divinity necessarily placed him well outside that realm. Moreover, the
polemical and often disparaging tone with which Abu Zayd addresses the work of
earlier, respected scholars, as well as his contemporaries, was seen as
unfitting for one supposedly working within the same tradition of moral
inquiry.
Additionally,
whereas for the writer cited above Islam is essential for defining the
social-political space in which practices of reason acquire their coherence,
Abu Zayd locates the limits to rational critique in the imperatives of the
secular nation-state:
They [the
Islamists] want to link religious apostasy with the crime of betraying the
nation; and so, they ignore an essential distinction: the freedom of human
beings to choose their religion--a freedom upheld by the Quran--and
"treason" aimed at harming the modern nation for the benefit of its
enemies.[39]
In other words,
Abu Zayd juxtaposes a desacralized and non-binding religion to the naturalized,
inviolable nation and its interests. So even though his challengers share with
Abu Zayd a commitment to the modern nation-state as a legitimate framework of
political practice and identity, their commitment is refracted through Islamic
principles and injunctions in a way that is absent from the writings of Abu
Zayd.
Central to Abu
Zayd's argument is an assertion about the incommensurability of reason and
religion, one contested by many of his critics. Thus, an article published
during the height of the controversy, for example, begins with the question:
are there conditions under which practical interest [maslaha], as
determined by human independent reasoning [`aql], justifies and requires
the temporary suspension of textual authority? Or, framing the issue in its
most conventional form: "by what measure do we define our interests [masalihana]?
Is it reason [`aql] or the religious text?"[40]
To work through this question, the author draws on a well-known historical
example--the temporary suspension of the prescribed punishment for thievery by
the second caliph, `Umar Ibn al-Khattab, during a period of acute
famine--reproducing the arguments of a number of classical scholars who studied
the case. The consensus of these scholars is that, given the conditions of
intense need produced by the famine, `Umar's decision was consonant with the
intentions of the text and did not constitute any sort of abrogation. This
argument devolves upon a discussion of the different categories of interest [maslaha],
particularly the distinction between those interests explicitly defined within
the text [al-masalih al-mu`atabira], and those left unmentioned but in
accord with its intentions [al-masalih al-mursala]. They argue that the presence
of great need, as the shari`a makes clear, changed the nature of the act
to where it could no longer be judged under the explicit rule pertaining to
thievery, but, instead, had to be assessed by reference to broader, more
general principles implied in the texts. Hence, contrary to the opinions of
some contemporary scholars, such cases do not demonstrate, nor authorize, any
sort of deviation from or rescindance of shari`a law.
From this
example the author concludes: "In truth, interests derived from human
reason, which contradict those embedded in the shari`a, are not but
illusory interests whose apparent rationality soon disappears when illuminated
by the light of the shari`a."[41]
In other words, real human interests cannot be uncovered by empirical
observation alone, but must also be consonant with divine intention. The split
which Abu Zayd posits between practical reality and sacred texts is replaced
here by a vision in which the two domains are thoroughly interwoven, a result
which requires the ongoing activity of interpretation by the members of the
believing community.
The exemplary
function of history depends upon a continuity of experience whereby expectations
and conditions remain relatively stable over long periods of time. In the case
of Islam, as the above discussion suggests, the possibility of such continuity
is underwritten by the divine status of the foundational text. Contrary to what
is frequently asserted, this historical perspective does not imply that each
generation is an exact replica of its predecessors, only that they resemble
each other in those aspects deemed essential by reason-guided interpreters of
the textual tradition. More importantly, we can now see that it is imperative
for a religious thinker working within such a tradition to pose the possibility
of God or the divine--even as a necessary act of faith--in order to set the
horizon within which reasoning may occur. It is the impossibility of taking
this step within the space defined by the modern concept of history which
animated much of the debate discussed above.
conclusion
The fact that many Egyptian intellectuals find
modernist renderings of Islam convincing bears witness to the now long-standing
project aimed at reorganizing the conceptual and material structures which
organize the daily practice and experience of non-Western peoples. Such
reorganization allows Muslims to consider the Quran inessential to the task of
ordering their social and political life, even as they continue to regard
themselves as religiously devout. This form of thinking, I would argue, is
consistent with modernist discourse that has privatized religious belief and
rendered divinity inconsequential to the organization of social life. Moreover,
it is not surprising that Islamic institutions are not forwarding a radical
alternative to this current world order. Given the kinds of forces brought to
bear on countries, like Egypt, that occupy dependent positions within the
structures of world capital, there are few possibilities for organizing society
along lines other than those consonant with these forces.
My aim in this
paper has not been as much to discuss Islamic social movements, as to examine
some of the conceptual dimensions used to analyze these movements.
Specifically, I have suggested that we need to pay closer attention to the
kinds of assumptions that accompany the frameworks and concepts we use; and
secondly, that we need to distinguish between Islam as a long-standing
tradition and the various expedient uses to which the term is being put, be it
by scholars, politicians, militants, or ordinary men and women. This does not
attribute an unchanging essence to Islam; rather it points to the need to
disentangle, in Wittgensteinian fashion, the disparate ideas and historical
forms which have come to be awkwardly subsumed under the term Islam.
This research
was assisted by a grant from the Joint Committee on Near and Middle East of the
Social Science Research Council and the American Council of Learned Societies
with funds provided by the U.S. Information Agency's Near and Middle East Research
and Training Act. In addition, the paper benefited greatly from the critical
responses of Marlene Hidalgo, as well as the editors of this volume, Saba
Mahmood and Nancy Reynolds. They bear none of the responsibility for its
shortcomings.
1.
Since the writing of this
article, the Egyptian Appellate Court has ruled in favor of the Islamist lawyer
who brought a suit against Abu Zayd. This suit required that Abu Zayd be
forcibly divorced from his wife on the grounds that he is an apostate. Abu
Zayd's lawyers are now appealing the case.
2.
Of course, there have
been exceptions to this general pattern, notably among anthropologists
interested in the idea of rationalities. Evans-Pritchard and Malinowski are two
early and well-known examples.
3.
Needless to say, the
instrumentalist view of language such an argument presupposes weds this
literature to a positivism few researchers would explicitly endorse.
4.
See, for example, Roger
Owen, State Power and Politics in the Making of the Modern Middle East,
Suny Series in the Social and Economic History of the Middle East (New York:
Routledge, 1994); Zachary Lockman, ed. Workers and Working Classes in the
Middle East (New York: SUNY P, 1994).
5.
Talal Asad, The Idea
of an Anthropology of Islam, Occasional Papers (Washington D.C.: Ctr. for
Contemporary Arab Studies, Georgetown, 1986). See also Alasdair MacIntyre, After
Virtue (Notre Dame: U of Notre Dame P, 1981).
6.
Admittedly, this
distinction cannot be made in any absolute sense. Nonetheless, I am simply suggesting
that it is theoretically and methodologically necessary for the analysis of
discursive traditions to be distinguished from the utilitarian and pragmatic
uses to which they are put.
7.
Those authors who point
to the manipulative use of Islamic vocabulary to clothe, what are in their
view, non-Islamic arguments are clearly addressing usages of this kind. The
concept of a discursive tradition directs us toward language use of a different
sort, one elaborated by Foucault with the concept of "discourse." See
The Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Harper,
1972).
8.
Most of the following
discussion is based on Abu Zayd's most recently published book, which figured
most significantly in the tenure committee's report: Naqd al-Khitab al- Dini
[The Critique of Religious Discourse] (Cairo: Dar al-Thaqafa al-Jadida,
1992). This work summarizes most of the central themes of Abu Zayd's earlier
writings. All translations from Arabic are mine.
9.
Zayd 93 (italics added).
10.
Zayd 96.
11.
Zayd 193.
12.
Zayd 56. Political
regimes of various types have often acknowledged the ultimate sovereignty of
God without finding it necessary to grant religious specialists authority over
all affairs of state.
13.
Zayd 30, 64-69.
14.
Zayd 30.
15.
Zayd 9, 102.
16.
Zayd 110.
17.
Zayd 9.
18.
Nasr Hamid Abu Zayd,
"Mat al-Rajul wa Bada'at Muhakamatuhu," Adab wa Naqd, Cairo
101 (January) 1994: 67.
19.
Zayd, Naqd
110-118.
20.
Zayd, Naqd
114-116. There are a number of Islamic knowledges--most importantly, asbab
al-nusul and nasikh wa mansukh--which attempt to clarify the context
surrounding revelation in order to guide the interpretation of the text. Abu
Zayd, applying the yardstick of modernist historiography, finds these
knowledges to be inadequate to the modern interpreter's task.
21.
It should be noted that
these two steps are grounded upon incompatible assumptions regarding the nature
of social reality--the first, objectivist; the second, phenomenological.
22.
Zayd, Naqd 9.
23.
Zayd, Naqd 53.
24.
For a number of
interesting analyses of the historical developments underlying our modern
concept of history, see Reinhart Kosselleck, Futures Past: On the Semantics
of Historical Time (Cambridge: MIT P, 1985).
25.
Kosselleck 214.
26.
On this point, see Nicholas
B. Dirks, "History as a Sign of the Modern," Public Culture
2.2 (Spring 1990): 25-33; Dipesh Chakrabarty, "The Death of History?
Historical Consciousness and the Culture of Late Capitalism," Public
Culture 4.2 (Spring 1992): 47-65.
27.
This expression comes
from Toqueville who observed in Democracy in America: "As the past
has ceased to throw its light upon the future, the mind of man wanders in
obscurity." Quoted in Kosselleck, 27.
28.
Not surprisingly, one of
the most common rebuffs given to those calling for the creation of an Islamic
state is precisely that they lack a real plan or program.
29.
Zayd, Naqd 61.
Note that texts may reflect reality, but are not an integral part of it.
30.
Zayd, Naqd.
31.
See Kristie McClure,
"Difference, Diversity, and the Limits of Toleration" Political
Theory 18.3 (August 1990): 361-392, for an excellent discussion of these
issues and their relevance to contemporary strategies of political activism.
32.
McClure 376.
33.
Chakrabarty 63.
34.
Admittedly, many Muslims
would concur with Abu Zayd on the ultimate unknowability of God; most, however,
would identify this as one of the epistemological conditions defining the task
of interpreting God's message and not as a justification for the abandonment of
that project.
35.
See, for example,
Nicholas B. Dirks, Colonialism and Culture (Ann Arbor: U of Michigan P,
1992); Timothy Mitchell, Colonising Egypt (Cambridge: Cambridge UP,
1988); Asad, Genealogies.
36.
This report was reprinted
in Al-Mujtam`a Al-Madani 18 (May 1993): 9- 13.
37.
Hence, an article by four
Cairo University professors, entitled "Scientific Report on the Views of
Nasr Hamid Abu Zayd," is prefaced by the following statement: "We
undertake this report on the views of Nasr Hamid Abu Zayd on the basis of our
identity as Muslims, believing in God and his Messenger (SAAS), commanded by
God to promote that which is allowed and prevent that which is forbidden; we
offer advice [nasiha] of God, of his messenger, and of his book to
Muslims each and all, as God demands of us that we pursue every legitimate
course to correct what is in error." In Abd al- Sabur Shahin, Qissa Abu
Zayd wa Inhisar al-`Almaniyya fi Jami`at al-Qahira [The Abu Zayd Affair and
Removal of Secularism at Cairo University] (Cairo: Dar Al-I'tisam, 1994) 112.
38.
Fahmi Howaydi,
"Hadhar min al-La`ab bil Nar," Al- Ahram (20 April, 1993).
39.
Zayd, Adab wa Naqd 65.
40.
Muhammad Ibrahim Mabruk,
"Al-Nas...Am al-Maslaha," Minbar al-Sharq, Cairo 8 (July
1993): 64.
41.
Mabruk 75.